By John Gray
An Appetite for Wonder: The Makings of a Scientist by Richard Dawkins (Ecco Press)
If an
autobiography can ever contain a true reflection of the author, it is
nearly always found in a throwaway sentence. When the world’s most
celebrated atheist writes of the discovery of evolution, Richard Dawkins
unwittingly reveals his sense of his mission in the world. Toward the
end of An Appetite for Wonder, the first installment in what is
meant to be a two-volume memoir, Dawkins cites the opening lines of the
first chapter of the book that made him famous, The Selfish Gene, published in 1976:
Intelligent life on a planet comes of an age when it first works out the reason for its own existence. If superior creatures from space ever visit earth, the first question they will ask, in order to assess the level of our civilisation, is: “Have they discovered evolution yet?” Living organisms had existed on earth, without ever knowing why, for over three thousand million years before the truth finally dawned on one of them. His name was Charles Darwin.
Several of
the traits that Dawkins displays in his campaign against religion are on
show here. There is his equation of superiority with cleverness: the
visiting aliens are more advanced creatures than humans because they are
smarter and know more than humans do. The theory of evolution by
natural selection is treated not as a fallible theory—the best account we have so far of how life emerged and developed—but
as an unalterable truth, which has been revealed to a single individual
of transcendent genius. There cannot be much doubt that Dawkins sees
himself as a Darwin-like figure, propagating the revelation that came to
the Victorian naturalist.
Among these
traits, it is Dawkins’s identification with Darwin that is most
incongruous. No two minds could be less alike than those of the great
nineteenth-century scientist and the latter-day evangelist for atheism.
Hesitant, doubtful, and often painfully perplexed, Darwin understood
science as an empirical investigation in which truth is never
self-evident and theories are always provisional. If science, for
Darwin, was a method of inquiry that enabled him to edge tentatively and
humbly toward the truth, for Dawkins, science is an unquestioned view
of the world. The Victorians are often mocked for their supposed
certainties, when in fact many of them (Darwin not least) were beset by
anxieties and uncertainties. Dawkins, by contrast, seems never to doubt
for a moment the capacity of the human mind—his own, at any rate—to resolve questions that previous generations have found insoluble.
Dawkins may not be Victorian, but the figure who emerges from An Appetite for Wonder
is in many ways decidedly old-fashioned. Before Dawkins’s own story
begins, the reader is given a detailed account of the Dawkins family
tree—perhaps a natural prelude for one involved
so passionately with genes, but slightly eccentric in a
twenty-first-century memoir. Dawkins’s description of growing up in
British colonial Africa, going on to boarding school and then to Oxford,
has a similarly archaic flavor and could easily have been written
before World War II. The style in which he recounts his early years has a
labored jocularity of a sort one associates with some of the stuffier
products of that era, who—dimly aware that they lacked any sense of humor—were determined to show they appreciated the lighter side of life.
Born
in 1941 in Nairobi, Kenya, and growing up in Nyasaland, now Malawi,
Dawkins writes of life in the colonies in glowingly idyllic terms: “We
always had a cook, a gardener and several other servants. ... Tea was
served on the lawn, with beautiful silver teapot and hot-water jug, and a
milk jug under a dainty muslin cover weighted down with periwinkle
shells sewn around the edges.” He remembers with special fondness the
head servant, Ali, who “loyally accompanied” the family in its travels,
and later became Dawkins’s “constant companion and friend.” Unlike the
best of the colonial administrators, some of whom were deeply versed in
the languages and histories of the peoples they ruled, Dawkins displays
no interest in the cultures of the African countries where he lived as a
boy. It is the obedient devotion of those who served his family that
has remained in his memory.
Loyal servants turn up at several points in Dawkins’s progress through life. When he arrives at Oxford, the porter at Balliol—a college that had demonstrated its intellectual credentials by admitting three members of his family—recalls
Dawkins’s father and two uncles but mistakes them for Dawkins’s
brothers. This, Dawkins tells us, showed the “timeless view”
characteristic of “that loyal and bowler-hatted profession.” He goes on
to recount an anecdote about a new recruit to the profession, who
recorded in his log-book of his duties how he could hear “rain banging
on me bowler hat while I did me rounds.” The tone of indulgent
superiority is telling. Dawkins is ready to smile on those he regards as
beneath him as long as it is clear who is on top.
It is a different matter when those he sees as his intellectual underlings—religious believers and any who stray from the strictest interpretation of Darwinism—refuse
to follow his lead. Recalling his years at boarding school, Dawkins
winces at the memory of the bullying suffered by a sensitive boy, “a
precociously brilliant scholar” who was reduced to “a state of
whimpering, abject horror” when he was stripped of his clothing and
forced to take cold baths. Today, Dawkins is baffled by the fact that he
didn’t feel sympathy for the boy. “I don’t recall feeling even secret
pity for the victim of the bullying,” he writes. Dawkins’s bafflement at
his lack of empathy suggests a deficiency in self-knowledge. As anyone
who reads his sermons against religion can attest, his attitude towards
believers is one of bullying and contempt reminiscent of the attitude of
some of the more obtuse colonial missionaries towards those they aimed
to convert.
Exactly how Dawkins became the
anti-religious missionary with whom we are familiar will probably never
be known. From what he writes here, I doubt he knows himself. Still,
there are a few clues. He began his pilgrimage to unbelief at the age of
nine, when he learned from his mother “that Christianity was one of
many religions and they contradicted each other. They couldn’t all be
right, so why believe the one in which, by sheer accident of birth, I
happened to be brought up?” But he was not yet ready to embrace atheism,
and curiously his teenage passion for Elvis Presley reinforced his
vestigial Christianity. Listening to Elvis sing “I Believe,” Dawkins was
amazed to discover that the rock star was religious. “I worshipped
Elvis,” he recalls, “and I was a strong believer in a non-denominational
creator god.” Dawkins confesses to being puzzled as to why he should
have been so surprised that Elvis was religious: “He came from an
uneducated working-class family in the American South. How could he not
have been religious?” By the time he was sixteen, Dawkins had “shed my
last vestige of theistic credulity.” As one might expect, the catalyst
for his final conversion from theism was Darwinism. “I became
increasingly aware that Darwinian evolution was a powerfully available
alternative to my creator god as an explanation of the beauty and
apparent design of life. ... It wasn’t long then before I became
strongly and militantly atheistic.”
What is
striking is the commonplace quality of Dawkins’s rebellion against
religion. In turning away from the milk-and-water Anglicanism in which
he had been reared—after his conversion from theism, he “refused to kneel in chapel,” he writes proudly—he
was doing what tens of thousands of Britain’s young people did at the
time. Compulsory religious instruction of the kind that exists in
British schools, it has often been observed, creates a fertile
environment for atheism. Dawkins’s career illustrates the soundness of
this truism. If there is anything remarkable in his adolescent
rebellion, it is that he has remained stuck in it. At no point has
Dawkins thrown off his Christian inheritance. Instead, emptying the
faith he was taught of its transcendental content, he became a
neo-Christian evangelist. A more inquiring mind would have noticed at
some point that religion comes in a great many varieties, with belief in
a creator god figuring in only a few of the world’s faiths and most
having no interest in proselytizing. It is only against the background
of a certain kind of monotheism that Dawkins’s evangelical atheism makes
any sense.
Even more remarkable is Dawkins’s
inveterate literal-mindedness. He tells us that “the Pauline belief that
everybody is born in sin, inherited from Adam (whose embarrassing
non-existence was unknown to St. Paul), is one of the very nastiest
aspects of Christianity.” It is true that the idea of original sin has
become one with a morbid preoccupation with sexuality, which has been
part of Christianity throughout much of its history. Even so, it is an
idea that contains a vital truth: evil is not error, a mistake of the
mind, a failure of understanding that can be corrected by smarter
thinking. It is something deeper and more constitutive of human life
itself. The capacity and propensity for destruction goes with being
human. One does not have to be religious to acknowledge this dark fact.
With his myth or metaphor of the death instinct thanatos, Freud—a lifelong atheist—recognized
that impulses of hatred and cruelty are integral to the human psyche.
As an atheist myself, it is a view I find no difficulty in sharing.
Quite
apart from the substance of the idea, there is no reason to suppose
that the Genesis myth to which Dawkins refers was meant literally.
Coarse and tendentious atheists of the Dawkins variety prefer to
overlook the vast traditions of figurative and allegorical
interpretations with which believers have read Scripture. Both Augustine
and before him the Jewish philosopher Philo of Alexandria explicitly
cautioned against literalism in interpreting the biblical creation
story. Later, in the twelfth century, Maimonides took a similar view. It
was only around the time of the Reformation that the idea that the
story was a factual account of events became widely held. When he
maintains that Darwin’s account of evolution displaced the biblical
story, Dawkins is assuming that both are explanatory theories—one
primitive and erroneous, the other more advanced and literally true. In
treating religion as a set of factual propositions, Dawkins is
mimicking Christianity at its most fundamentalist.
There
is an interesting inconsistency between Dawkins’s dismissal of religion
as being little more than a tissue of falsehood and his adherence to an
evolutionary account of human behavior. In the later chapters of An Appetite for Wonder,
Dawkins recounts his work on the behavior of blowflies, and later mice,
guppy fish, and crickets. As always, what he describes as his
“Darwin-obsessed brain” analyzed these behaviors in terms that were
meant to be consistent with Darwinian orthodoxy. His best-selling
manifesto The Selfish Gene originated in 1973, when strike
action by miners led to a “three-day week” in which there were frequent
power-cuts. Dawkins needed electricity for his work on crickets, but he
could do without it for writing, which he did on a portable typewriter,
so he began to write instead. By 1982, we find him “trying to push
Universal Darwinism”—the view that genes are not the only replicators in natural selection—a
theme he had explored in the last chapter of his best-seller, where he
presented his theory of memes. Dawkins’s suggestion is that memes “leap
from brain to brain, via a process which, in the broad sense, can be
called imitation,” and it is clear that he sees this process at work throughout human culture, including religion.
There
are many difficulties in talk of memes, including how they are to be
identified. Is Romanticism a meme? Is the idea of evolution itself a
meme, jumping unbidden from brain to brain? My suspicion is that the
entire “theory” amounts to not much more than a misplaced metaphor. The
larger problem is that a meme-based Darwinian account of religion is at
odds with Dawkins’s assault on religion as a type of intellectual error.
If Darwinian evolution applies to religion, then religion must have
some evolutionary value. But in that case there is a tension between
naturalism (the study of humans and other animals as organisms in the
natural world) and the rationalist belief that the human mind can rid
itself of error and illusion through a process of critical reasoning. To
be sure, Dawkins and those who think like him will object that
evolutionary theory tells us how we got where we are, but does not
preclude our taking charge of ourselves from here on. But who are “we”?
In a passage from The Selfish Gene that Dawkins quotes in this memoir, he writes:
They are in you and me; they created us, body and mind; and their preservation is the ultimate rationale for our existence. They have come a long way, these replicators. Now they come by the name of genes, and we are their survival machines.
If
we “are” survival machines, it is unclear how “we” can decide anything.
The idea of free will, after all, comes from religion and not from
science. Science may give us the unvarnished truth—or some of it—about
our species. Part of that truth may prove to be that humans are not and
can never be rational animals. Religion may be an illusion, but that
does not mean science can dispel it. On the contrary, science may well
show that religion cannot be eradicated from the human mind.
Unsurprisingly, this is a possibility that Dawkins never explores.
For
all his fervent enthusiasm for science, Dawkins shows very little
interest in asking what scientific knowledge is or how it comes to be
possible. There are many philosophies of science. Among them is
empiricism, which maintains that scientific knowledge extends only so
far as observation and experiment can reach; realism, which holds that
science can give an account of parts of the world that can never be
observed; irrealism, according to which there is no one truth of things
to which scientific theories approximate; and pragmatism, which views
science theories as useful tools for organizing and controlling
experience. If he is aware of these divergent philosophies, Dawkins
never discusses them. His attitude to science is that of a practitioner
who does not need to bother with philosophical questions.
It
is worth noting, therefore, that it is not as a practicing scientist
that Dawkins has produced his assaults against religion. As he makes
clear in this memoir, he gave up active research in the 1970s when he
left his crickets behind and began to write The Selfish Gene.
Ever since, he has written as an ideologue of scientism, the
positivistic creed according to which science is the only source of
knowledge and the key to human liberation. He writes well—fluently,
vividly, and at times with considerable power. But the ideas and the
arguments that he presents are in no sense novel or original, and he
seems unaware of the critiques of positivism that appeared in its
Victorian heyday.
Some of them bear re-reading
today. One of the subtlest and most penetrating came from the pen of
Arthur Balfour, the Conservative statesman, British foreign secretary,
and sometime prime minister. Well over a century ago, Balfour identified
a problem with the evolutionary thinking that was gaining ascendancy at
the time. If the human mind has evolved in obedience to the imperatives
of survival, what reason is there for thinking that it can acquire
knowledge of reality, when all that is required in order to reproduce
the species is that its errors and illusions are not fatal? A purely
naturalistic philosophy cannot account for the knowledge that we believe
we possess. As he framed the problem in The Foundations of Belief
in 1895, “We have not merely stumbled on truth in spite of error and
illusion, which is odd, but because of error and illusion, which is even
odder.” Balfour’s solution was that naturalism is self-defeating:
humans can gain access to the truth only because the human mind has been
shaped by a divine mind. Similar arguments can be found in a number of
contemporary philosophers, most notably Alvin Plantinga. Again, one does
not need to accept Balfour’s theistic solution to see the force of his
argument. A rigorously naturalistic account of the human mind entails a
much more skeptical view of human knowledge than is commonly
acknowledged.
Balfour’s contributions to the debate about science and religion are nowadays little known—compelling
testimony to the historical illiteracy of contemporary philosophy. But
Balfour also testifies to how shallow, crass, and degraded the debate
has become since Victorian times. Unlike most of those who debated then,
Dawkins knows practically nothing of the philosophy of science, still
less about theology or the history of religion. From his point of view,
he has no need to know. He can deduce everything he wants to say from
first principles. Religion is a type of supernatural belief, which is
irrational, and we will all be better off without it: for all its
paraphernalia of evolution and memes, this is the sum total of Dawkins’s
argument for atheism. His attack on religion has a crudity that would
make a militant Victorian unbeliever such as T.H. Huxley—described by his contemporaries as “Darwin’s bulldog” because he was so fierce in his defense of evolution—blush scarlet with embarrassment.
If
religion comes in many varieties, so too does atheism. Dawkins takes
for granted that being an atheist goes with having liberal values (with
the possible exception of tolerance). But as the Victorians well knew,
there are many types of atheism, liberal and illiberal, and many
versions of atheist ethics. Again, Dawkins imagines an atheist is bound
to be an enemy of religion. But there is no necessary connection between
atheism and hostility to religion, as some of the great Victorian
unbelievers understood. More intelligent than their latter-day disciple,
the positivists tried to found a new religion of humanity—especially
August Comte (1798–1857), who established a secular church in Paris
that for a time found converts in many other parts of the world. The new
religion was an absurdity, with rituals being practiced that were based
on the pseudo-science of phrenology—but at least the positivists understood that atheism cannot banish human needs that only faith can meet.
One
might wager a decent sum of money that it has never occurred to Dawkins
that to many people he appears as a comic figure. His default mode is
one of rational indignation—a stance of
withering patrician disdain for the untutored mind of a kind one might
expect in a schoolmaster in a minor public school sometime in the 1930s.
He seems to have no suspicion that any of those he despises could find
his stilted pose of indignant rationality merely laughable. “I am not a
good observer,” he writes modestly. He is referring to his observations
of animals and plants, but his weakness applies more obviously in the
case of humans. Transfixed in wonderment at the workings of his own
mind, Dawkins misses much that is of importance in human beings—himself and others.
To
the best of my recollection, I have met Dawkins only once and by
chance, when we coincided at some meeting in London. It must have been
in late 2001, since conversation at dinner centered around the terrorist
attacks of September 11. Most of those at the table were concerned with
how the West would respond: would it retaliate, and if so how? Dawkins
seemed uninterested. What exercised him was that Tony Blair had invited
leaders of the main religions in Britain to Downing Street to discuss
the situation—but somehow omitted to ask a
leader of atheism (presumably Dawkins himself) to join the gathering.
There seemed no question in Dawkins’s mind that atheism as he understood
it fell into the same category as the world’s faiths.
In
this, Dawkins is surely right. To suppose that science can liberate
humankind from ignorance requires considerable credulity. We know how
science has been used in the past—not only to
alleviate the human lot, but equally to serve tyranny and oppression.
The notion that things might be fundamentally different in the future is
an act of faith—one as gratuitous as any of the
claims of religion, if not more so. Consider Pascal. One of the
founders of modern probability theory and the designer of the world’s
first mass-transit system, he was far too intelligent to imagine that
human reason could resolve perennial questions. His celebrated wager has
always seemed to me a rather bad bet. Since we cannot know what gods
there may be (if any), why stake our lives on pleasing one of them? But
Pascal’s wager was meant as a pedagogical device rather than a
demonstrative argument, and he reached faith himself by way of skeptical
doubt. In contrast, Dawkins shows not a trace of skepticism anywhere in
his writings. In comparison with Pascal, a man of restless intellectual
energy, Dawkins is a monument to unthinking certitude.
We
must await the second volume of his memoirs to discover how Dawkins
envisions his future. But near the end of the present volume, an
inadvertent remark hints at what he might want for himself. Darwin was
“never Sir Charles,” he writes, “and what an amazing indictment of our
honours system that is.” It is hard to resist the thought that the
public recognition that in Britain is conferred by a knighthood is
Dawkins’s secret dream. A life peerage would be even better. What could
be more fitting for this tireless evangelist than to become the
country’s officially appointed atheist, seated alongside the bishops in
the House of Lords? He may lack their redeeming tolerance and display
none of their sense of humor, but there cannot be any reasonable doubt
that he belongs in the same profession.
John Gray is emeritus professor of European thought at the London School of Economics and author of The Silence of Animals: On Progress and Other Modern Myths (Farrar, Straus, and Giroux).
No comments:
Post a Comment